The Psychological Foundation of Economics: the History of Consumer Theory
Citation:
W. Fred van Raaij (1985) ,"The Psychological Foundation of Economics: the History of Consumer Theory", in SV - Historical Perspective in Consumer Research: National and International Perspectives, eds. Jagdish N. Sheth and Chin Tiong Tan, Singapore : Association for Consumer Research, Pages: 8-13.
[W. Fred van Raaij is professor of economic. psychology, Erasmus University, Department of Economics, P.O. Box 1738, 3000 DR Rotterdam, The Netherlands. He is editor of the Journal of Economic Psychology.] Several attempts have been made to base economic (consumer) theory on a better psychological foundation. The revolution of the 1920s has failed. It merely led to a reinforcement of the hard core of economic theory. Apart from this, consumer research developed in marketing, mainly based on a social and behavioral approach. This approach is still successful in solving practical problems and is integrated in "grand theories." A second revolution under the label of "behavioral economics" is under way and could use behavioral consumer research, which is in the 1980s in a better shape than Psychology was in the 1920s. INTRODUCTION The history of science is more than a chronological story of how science developed by accumulation of findings, models, and theories. Traditionally, "growth of knowledge" theories tell the history of economics, social sciences, and consumer theory as an offspring of both economics and social sciences. "Growth of knowledge" theories may describe the actual evolution of science, in a way a historian may describe the history of WWII. However, the historical accounts of the evolution of science are not neutral and unbiased. The historian is largely selective, what to include and what to be left out, The historian may attribute developments to persons that influenced the course of scientific developments. A marxist historian is more likely to attribute developments to underlying societal and economic forces, in this case the exploitation of consumers by multinational corporations. A third attribution is the attribution to the Zeitgeist, cultural developments influencing the direction of science. The history of science is interwoven with the epistemology of science, i.e. the way new knowledge is acquired and accepted in the scientific community. Epistemology may be defined as the "science of science," the study of how scientists select research topics; how scientists communicate through journals and conferences; how referees or "invisible colleges" determine what is "good science" (and should be published); and how scientists proceed with their work at the frontiers or rear-guards of research. Epistemology cannot be studied without reference to the methodology of science. The deductive methodology of mathematics, and the hypothetico-deductive method of astronomy and physics are examples for many economists and social scientists. For a large part, however, social scientists use an inductive approach of "fact finding" and generalization. in this contribution, attention should be paid to the methodology of consumer theory and research. The methodology largely determines, how scientific research proceeds by verification or by falsification of theories and hypotheses, and by changes in the dominant paradigm (Kuhn 1970) or research program (Lakatos 1968). In this paper, the development of consumer research in economics, in marketing, and in consumer policy is described from a historical, epistemological, and methodological viewpoint. It may be clear that this is too large a task in a limited number of pages. Hopefully, I traced the major developments, but as I am selective and biased myself, others might provide their differing viewpoints. EPISTEMOLOGICAL APPROACHES 1. Karl Popper Popper's principal problem was to demarcate science from non-science, In his Logik der Forschung (1934) Popper replaced the Vienna-Circle=s principle of verifiability by the principle of falsifiability, as a test of a genuine scientific hypothesis. This is in accordance with common statistical theory of testing and rejecting hypotheses. From a theory, one or more hypotheses may be derived; after the operationalization of concepts, the hypothesis may be tested with empirical data. A rejection of the hypothesis brings "deadly" evidence to the theory, which should be adapted or rejected. Science is not to "proof" anything, as common sense assumes, but is to "disproof" hypotheses. A hypothesis stands upright, as long as no disproof has been found. Popper gradually evolved a powerful anti-inductionist view of science as an endless dialectical sequence of "conjectures and refutations" (Blaug 1976). Is a single refutation enough to discard a theory? A hasty reading of Popper's work may lead to this
Friedman (1953) is a Popperian with an F-twist applied to economics. He defends the apparently absurd idea that "unreal assumptions" are not a vice but a virtue. The more significant the theory, the more unrealistic the assumptions. Economic theory starts from assumptions mainly about consumer and producer behavior. Whereas the Popperian emphasis is on falsification of outcomes (hypotheses, predictions), assumptions do not matter so much. Friedman's argument, the F-twist, sparked off a vigorous controversy. A veridical description of reality matters less than correct predictions. Musgrave (1981) untwists the F-twist by distinguishing negligibility, domain, and heuristic assumptions in economic theory, Assumptions may be "unreal" in the beginning of theory development but by successive approximation assumptions will be replaced by more veridical assumptions.
2. Tbomas Kuhn
In Kuhn's Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1970, second edition), the emphasis shifts, from the methodology of falsification to positive history. The principle of "tenacity" is no longer the exception but the rule. "Normal science," in Kuhn is terminology, is problem-solving activity in the context of an accepted theoretical framework or paradigm. By accident more than by planning, anomalies to the dominant paradigm are obtained. A few anomalies or unexplainable findings do not discomfort most scientists. The phenomena are stochastic, anyway. A series of "anomalistic" findings may start critical thinking and after some time a revolution or the overthrow of the current paradigm by a new and hopefully better one.
For Popper, science is in a permanent state of revolution. For Kuhn, the history of science is marked by long periods of steady refinement, interrupted by discontinuous jumps, hopefully jumps forward, or revolutions. In a revolutionary period, the old and the new paradigm are in conflict. If the new paradigm is more fruitful and successful in solving hitherto unsolved problems, the new paradigm will certainly win. Conversion of .scientists to the new paradigm resemples a religious conversion; it is a emotional and difficult transition from the former to the new paradigm. Many scientists of an older generation refuse to he converted and remain believing in the former degenerating paradigm.
What is a paradigm? Kuhn employs the term for the choice of problems and methodology. In place, he is going so far to give it a wider meaning of Weltanschauung or basic philosophy. The appropriate definition is "the entire constellation of beliefs, values, techniques, and so on, shared by the members of a given community"(Kuhn 1970, p. 173).
In astronomy and physics, the Copernican, Newtonian, and Einstein-Planck revolutions come to mind. In chemistry, Lavoisier might have caused a revolution. The Copernican revolution took 150 years to become accepted. Modern revolutions will probably take shorter to become accepted. Paradigmatic changes are not really discontinuous; the former and the new paradigm may exist together for a long period.
Important in Kuhn's arguments is the role of values in scientific judgments and reference groups ("invisible colleges") as determinants of scientific behavior. Intergenerational conflicts play a role as well. Younger scientists will normally be the first to accept the new paradigm. Being the first to accept the new paradigm may create problems in getting one's manuscripts accepted in established scientific journals. Early adopters of the new paradigm may have a lead to others with their publications. Believers in the old paradigm will gradually lose to the new generation, because their solutions and methodology becomes less and less accepted.
3. Irnre Lakatos
Lakatos' (1970) approach is a compromise between Popper's "aggressive methodology" and Kuhn's "defensive methodology." See also Lakatos and Musgrave (1970). Lakatos starts stating that isolated theories and hypotheses are inappropriate units of appraisal. What ought to be appraised are clusters of interrelated theories or scientific research programs (SRP). A SRP is an organic unity, consisting of a "hard core," a "positive heuristic," and a "protective belt." The hard core and the positive heuristic are essential parts of a research program. Giving them up means abandoning the research program. Non-essential, replacable components belong to the protective belt. Changes in the protective belt of a research program are favorably judged only if they are theoretically or empirically progressive. A progressive change is an extended theory that explains more phenomena than the former theory.
Progressive changes in the protective belt are welcomed in the process of normal science. Changes in the hard core or positive heuristic are revolutionary and cause the death of a research program or the replacement by a new research program.
The hard core specifies the fundamental characteristics of a research program, cf. Kuhn's paradigm. The positive heuristic is a "normative" hard core: A set of imperatives which contain guidance as to how the reserch program should unfold, how it should he defended, what falls within and what falls outside its scope (Latsis 1976). Note that the hard core of a research program cannot really be falsified.
Research programs may degenerate, astrology for example. Now research programs may develop, Popper, Kuhn, and Lakatos find most of their examples from physics, and are rather negative about economics and social sciences, as "pre-paradigmatic proto-sciences."
CONSUMER THEORY IN ECONOMICS
During the second half of the 19th century three major developments took place in psychology (Coats 1976): James' (1890) conception of the physiological-biological determinants of human behavior; McDougall's, (1908) instinct theory; and Watson's (1913) behaviorism. At about the same time, the new subjective" theories of value (the so-called marginal revolution) were being assimilated into economic theory.
As economics is or should be a social science, the new psychological approaches should be integrated in economic theory that was so far based on a naive type of hedonism. In the period 1880-1920, the proponents of a better psychological foundation of economics, notably Veblen (1919), attacked the defenders of the "orthodox" economic theory. These defenders did not form one homogeneous group. Some economists flatly denied that any psychology was relevant for economics as a science, arguing that economics should concentrate on "catallactics," the science of exchanges, in which prices are the only elements to be included, without reference to consumer or entrepreneurial motivations. Some other economists took "a priori" positions. They wanted to start from basic assumptions about human behavior, and these basic assumptions are: rationality, complete knowledge, and utility maximization. Although it may be clear that these assumptions are not very realistic, they might nevertheless be good starting points for theorizing. If hypotheses (predictions) from the theory are refuted, the assumptions may be relaxed. Assumptions are heuristic in this sense. They are a starting point and not a dogma. Whereas simple theories are preferred over complex ones (Occam's razor), one should start with simple, albeit unrealistic,-assumptions.
The opponents (Veblen 1919) asked for a wholesale reconstruction of the foundations of economics. Veblen's devastating satirical portrayal of the hedonistic conception of man as responding passively to external stimuli was persuasive, when juxtaposed against the actively intelligent interpretation of human nature by James. The critics' proposals included the following propositions and procedures (Coats 1976):
1. Employ methods similar or identical to those used in the natural sciences.
2. Adopt 'realistic' fundamental assumptions, i.e. assumptions compatible with observed behavior or consistent with psychological findings.
3. Derive assumptions from psychological research into the actual behavior and motivations of consumers.
4. Abandon efforts to formulate abstract, general theories and concentrate on the development of middle-level, empirically-grounded theories,
5. Develop empirically testable theories which will serve as a basis for scientific explanation, prediction, and/or control.
6. Undertake systematic empirical studies as a basis for formulating sound empirical generalizations and for testing and, if necessary, reformulating established theories.
7. Wherever possible, replace static theories by dynamic theories, accounting for change.
8. Broaden the scope of economic theory to take account of the social forces influencing economic behavior.
9. Go beyond prices and exchange values to examine the influence of market and non-market forces on economic and social welfare.
The first five propositions constitute the hard core of this rival research program (paradigm), since they could not be given up without abandoning the entire program. Propositions 6 and 9 comprise the positive heuristic, i.e. the guidelines how to develop the research program both theoretically and empirically. Propositions 7 and 8 illustrate the kind of problem shift entailed by the new program.
Hedonism was repudiated as a valid psychological theory. Veblen (1919) cum suis proposed a more objective and empirical-approach to the study of economic behavior. However, the defenders were more united than the attackers. Fisher (1892) disliked "this foisting of psychology on economics." "It is not the economist',,; province to build a theory of psychology. Antecedents of preference lay completely within the realm of psychology. it
Knight(1921a) asserts that many psychological theories are irrelevant to economics as a science, for "the basis of a science of conduct must be fixed principles of action, enduring and stable motives." Although Knight admits that "it is doubtful, if this is fundamentally the character of human life".(Knigbt 1921a). Knight accepts the "severe limitations" of economics as a science that economics is not about the content of economic behavior, but establishes laws universally valid as to its form. The attackers, trying to base economics on psychologically sound foundations, did not make constructive proposals, according to Knight, The strictures are valid as limitations, not as negations. "The principles of the established economics are partial statements, but sound as far as they go, and they go about as far as general principles can be carried" (Knight 1921b).
Nor all defenders of traditional economic theory accepted all of Knight's arguments. Most of them were less subtle and less interested in epistemological and methodological issues. By the end of the 1920s it was clear that the ambitious efforts to infuse psychology into economics or to reconstruct basic economic theory, employing new psychological findings, had manifestly failed (Coats 1976). Psychology was at that time still in a unsettled state, and the efforts may have been over-ambitious and premature.
The development of the Slutzky-Hicks-Allen indifference. curve analysis and, after WWII, econometric methodology ("the formalist revolution") seemed to confirm that psychology had little or nothing to contribute to the theoretical development of economics as a science. Already in 1915, Slutzky declared that "if we wish to place economics upon a solid basis, we must make it completely independent of psychological assumptions and philosophical hypotheses."
Although the attackers "lost , their attack was not without consequences for the bastion of economic theory. During the debate the hard core of economic theory was not merely preserved intact. It was reinforced. The key concepts were more carefully specified. The protective belt of auxiliary hypotheses was strengthened by the elimination of unnecessary propositions. The fundamental assumption of "economic man" was reformulated as "rationality" or the "logic of choice." Veblen disdainfully dismissed this as "pecuniary logic." This restoration of the basic theory was an essential prerequisite for its later econometric development.
By the end of the 1920s the hard core of orthodox economic demand theory has emerged in roughly the following propositions:
1. Basic economic theory is necessarily abstract, static, and general in form.
2. The fundamental assumptions must therefore be simple, uniform, and constant; they can neither be 'realistic' nor subject to falsification.
3. It is assumed that consumers aim to maximize their utility (satisfaction).
4. Consumers have limited budgets.
5. Consumers have unlimited wants in general, but experience diminishing marginal utility from consuming successive units of a good.
6. Consumers have perfect knowledge of relevant market conditions (prices, etc.).
7. Consumers make rational calculations, adjusting their expenditures at the margin.
8. Individual decisions are independent of those of others,
The positive heuristic, in Lakatosian terms, consists of the following recommendations:
9. Construct static models.
10. Reduce the numbers of assumptions to a minimum, including psychological assumptions.
11. Develop general theories.
12. Concentrate on the analysis of exchange values.
13. Reinterpret the theory to take account of discrepancies between the assumptions and the facts in order to improve predictions.
Although economic orthodoxy won over the heterodox psychology-oriented reformers in the 1920s, it might have been a Pyrrhus victory. Katona (1953) and Simon (1963) reopened the debate. To cite Simon (1963, p, 709,711):
Economics has been moving steadily into newer areas where the power of the orthodox model has never been demonstrated and where its adequacy must be considered anew... Orthodox economics was highly successful in handling small-maze problems without depending on psychology. New societal issues require the cooperation of the economist and the psychologist, employing cognitive theory.
The economic theory of consumer demand still serves as a basis for microeconomics. Later refinements are Lancaster's (1966) approach to handle goods as bundles of attributes rather than indivisible entities. Ratchford (1979) translated Lancaster's approach to consumer behavior research. A good example of a textbook in the microeconomic tradition is Deaton and Muellbauer (1980). Modern developments of the microeconomic approach to the study of consumer behavior are the Chicago School (Becker 1981).
Criticism remains with the fundamental assumptions of maximizing behavior, the unwillingness to consider the processes of individual and group decision making, the neglect to study interactions within the household and between households, the changes of tastes and preferences, the interaction of mass media and conversation, and so on. Some economists move in these directions, e.g. including the costs of information acquisition and the "costs of thinking" (Shugan 1980).
Economic theory is not degenerating, in Lakatosian terminology, but largely remains form rather than content, optimalization rather than description, abstract rather than concrete. As Ferber (1973) argued, it might still be fruitful to start from a parsimonious (economical) economic model of the income-consumption relationships, the so-called "income hypotheses" (Sheth, Van Raaij, and Wandwossen 1979), and improve the relationship by a process of successive approximation.
CONSUMER THEORY IN MARKETING
At first, the practical needs of marketers were (partly) satisfied by "motivation theory," applying psychoanalytical concepts and depth-interview methodology. The model of the consumer in motivation theory is largely irrational. Behavior is not governed by rational decision making , but by subconscious motives as a sublimation of sexual drives. Motivation theory provided a picture of the consumer that is completely different from orthodox economic theory. In no way, these two extremes could be reconciled. The dominance of the psychoanalytical school in psychology in the beginning of this century might have been a major obstacle for basing economic theory on psychological principles. Between 1940 and 1960, motivation theory had a successful period of application in consumer behavior research (Dichter 1964; Martineau 1958).
The period 1960-1966 might be characterized as the period of the "single construct" approaches. With a single construct, e.g. cognitive dissonance or perceived risk, researchers tried to explain parts of consumer behavior. Being successful in some instances, a single-construct approach will usually fail to provide a comprehensive picture of consumer behavior.
In 1964, a memorable meeting was organized at the University of California at Berkeley. At this meeting a number of scientists tried to integrate the separate findings into a "research program." At least they succeeded to integrate the findings into one or more "grand models" (Andreasen 1965; Nicosia 1966). These models could be applied, tested, and improved, and - an implicit research program was under way. A more elaborated model was developed by Howard and Sheth (1969) as the outcome of a large-scale (industrial and consumer) buyer behavior research project at Columbia University.
If these approaches constitute a research program. their hard core may be characterized with the following propositions:
1, Consumers have incomplete and selective percept ions of market conditions.
2. Consumers process information, develop choice criteria, distinguish product attributes, and intend to be rational.
3. Consumers learn from their experiences, partly by trial and error.
4. Consumers interact with each other,
5. The theory should be moderately abstract. Con structs may have different levels of abstraction.
The fifth proposition is in fact part of the positive heuristic. The positive heuristic of this research program is its empirical and hypothesis-testing orientation. Consumer behavior is at first a field to apply sociological, anthropological, and psychological theories in an eclectic manner. But after a number of years, consumer behavior could become a science of its own, with some original methodology, e.g. panel methods. Although some studies have been done to compare and to test the "grand Theories" (e.g., Farley and King 1970; Zaltman, Pinson, and Angelmar 1973), the major function of the grand theories is to integrate research findings and to stimulate research on parts of the models. A fourth function is the provision of a context for single-construct studies. A last but not the least function, especially of the Howard-Sheth model, is to demonstrate that theoretical constructs may have multiple meanings and functions. "Attitude" is both an intervening construct within the model and a hypothetical construct (as output of the model).
Later textbooks (Engel, Kollat, and Blackwell 1968 Hansen 1972) employed models for educational purposes. The EKB model, after some revisions in subsequent editions, became a "grand theory" of its own.
The period 1972-1980 could be characterized by the dominance of information-processing research, starting with Hansen's (1972) textbook-and ending with Bettman's (1979) comprehensive overview. The attitude model of Fishhein and Ajzen (1975) is popular as well. The model of the consumer in this period is the active decision maker, suggesting that consumption is a high-involvement activity. This approach has already been criticized bv Krugman (1968) and others, emphasizing that much consumer behavior is in fact low-involvement behavior In recent years, more studies on low-involvement reactions and affective factors have been published.
The positive heuristic of consumer research in marketing is that, apart from a few comprehensive theories, most empirical studies are of a "middle-level" nature, applicable to a domain of consumer behavior. The accumulation of these studies, notably on the attitude-behavior relationship and on consumer information processing, have brought a better insight in the determinants of consumer choice, product usage, and disposition. A second generation of "grand Theories" may be expected to integrate these research findings of the 1970s and 1980s.
CONCLUSIONS
The battle of the 1920s was lost. Psychology, then, was still in an unsettled stage, dominated by extreme schools, such as behaviorism on the one hand and psychoanalysis on the other hand. Psychology (Which psychology?) was not infused into economics. Economics as a science developed along the SlutzkyHicks-Allen lines of indifference curves and econometric methodology. Microeconomics became a mathematical jewel in a glass case, without much practical usability.
Along completely different lines, and in the beginning as a psychoanalytical reaction to the economic maximalization principles, behavioral consumer research developed in a marketing context. Marketing, at least in the U.S., is not a part of economics, but part of business administration. The practical usefulness of these studies for marketing management and consumer policy is evident. The Association for Consumer Research (ACR) is one of the major organizations in this area. Not only consumer policy, but "government policy" in general may benefit from this development. Studies on tax paying, investment and entrepreneurial behavior has strong similarities to consumer research, being similar in theory and methodology, cf. the Journal of Economic Psychology.
One may expect that in the future economists, dissatisfied with the usefulness of microeconomic consumer theory, find behavioral consumer research a good substitute for microeconomic consumer research. Behavioral consumer research and psychological research in 1985 are in a much better shape than psychological research was in 1920. Some indications of this direction are the foundation of the Society for the Advancement of Behavioral Economics (SABE)in 1983. SABE promotes the application of the behavioral sciences to economic problems and wants to replace unreal assumptions in economic theory by behavioral assumptions. We expect and hope that this second revolution will be more successful than the revolution of the 1920s.
REFERENCES
Andreasen, A.R. (1965), "Attitudes and customer behavior: A decision model," in L.E. Preston (ed), New Research in Marketing, Berkeley CA: IBER, University of California, pp. 1-16.
Becker, G.S. (1981), A Treatise on the Family, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
Bettman, J.R. (1979), An Information-processingTheory of Consumer Choice, Reading MA: Addison1-Wesley.
Blaug, 11. (1976), "Kulin versus Lakatos or Paradigms versus Research programmes," in S.J. Latsis (ed), Method and Appraisal in Economics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 149-180.
Coats, A.W. (1976), "Economics-and psychology: The death and resurrection of a research programme," in S.,T. Latsis (ed), Method and Appraisal in Economics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 43-64.
Deaton, A. and J. Muellbauer (1980), Economics and Consumer Behaviour, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dicliter, E. (1964), Handbook of Consumer Motivations, New York NY: McGraw-Hill.
Engel, J.F., D.T. Kollat and R.D. Blackwell (1968), Consumer Behavior, New York NY: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.
Farley, J.U. and L,W, Ring (1970), An empirical test of the Howard-Sheth model of buyer behavior, Journal of, Marketing Research, 7, 427-438.
Ferber, R. (1973), Consumer economics: A survey, Journal of Economic Literature, 11, 1303-1342.
Fisher, 1. (1,1392), Mathematical investigations in the theory of value and prices, Transactions of the Connecticut AcaderT\7, 9.
Fishbein, M. and 1. Ajzen (1975), Belief, attitude, intention, and behavior: An introduction to theory _~_nd research, Reading MA: Addison-Wesley.
Friedman, M. (1953), Essays in positive economics, Chicago IL: University of Chicago Press.
Hansen, F. (1972), Consumer choice-behavior, a cognitive theory, New York NY: T~e Free Press.
Howard, J.A. and J.N. Sheth (1969), The theory of buyer behavior, New York NY: Wiley,
James, W. (1890), The principles of psychology, New York NY: Dover Tr-eprint 1950).
Katona, G. (1953), Rational behavior and economic behavior, Psychological Review, 60, 307-318.
Knight, F.H. (1921a), Risk, uncertainty and profit, New York NY: Harper & Row.
Knight, F.H. (1921b), Traditional economic theory: Discussion, American Economic Review, Supplement, 11, 143-147.
Knight, F.H. (1931), "The relations of utility theory to economic method in the work of William Stanley Jevons and others," in S.A. Rice (ed), Methods in Social Science: A Case Book, Chicago: Social Science Research Council, pp. 59-69.
Krugman, H.E. (1968), Processes underlying exposure to advertising, American Psychologist, 23, 245-253.
Kuhn, T.S. (1970), The structure of scientific revolutions, International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, Vol. 2, Number 2, Chicago: University of Chicago Press (second edition).
Lakatos, 1. (1968) Criticism and the methodology of scientific research programmes, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 69, 149-186.
Lakatos, 1. and A.E. Musgrave (eds), Criticism and the growth of knowledge, Cambridge: Cambridge U-niversity Press, 1970.
Lancaster, K.J. (1966), A new approach to consumer theory, Journal of Political Economy 74 132-157.
Latsis, S.J. (1976), "A research programme in economics," in S.J. Latsis (ed), Method and Appraisal in Economics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1-41.
Martineau, P. (1958), The personality of the retail store, Harvard Business Review, 36, 47-55.
McDougall, W. (1908), An Introduction to Social Psychology, Boston: Luce.
Musgrave, R.A. (1981), 'Unreal assumptions' in economic theory: The F-twist untwisted, Kyklos, 34, 377-387.
Nicosia, F.M. (1966), Consumer decision processes: Marketing and advertising implications, Englewood Cliffs NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Popper, K.R. (1934), Logik der Forschung, Tubingen: Mohr (reprint 1966).
Ratchford, B.T. (1979), Operationalizing economic models of demand for product characteristics, Journal of Consumer Research, 6, 76-85.
Sheth, J.N., W.F. van Raaij and K. Wandwossen (1979), Income hypotheses and consumption, Papers on Economic Psychology 4. Erasmus University Rotterdam.
Shugan, S.M. (1980), The cost of thinking, Journal of Consumer Research, 7, 99-111.
Simon, H.A. (1963), "Economics and Psychology," in S. Koch (ed), Psychology: A study of a science, Vol. 6, New York NY: McGraw-Hill, pp. 685-723.
Slutzky, E.V. (1915). "On the theory of the budget of the consumer," in R.B. Ekelund, E.G. Furubotn & W.P. Gramm (eds), The evolution of modern demand theory, Lexington MA: Heath (reprint 1972).
Veblen, T. (1919), The place of science in modern civilisation, New York NY: B.1%7. Huebsch.
Watson, J.B. (1913), Psychology as a behaviorist views it, Psychological Review, 20, 158-177.
Zaltman, G., C.R.A. Pinson and R. Angelmar (1973), Metatheory and consumer research, Hinsdale IL: The Dryden Press.
----------------------------------------
Authors
W. Fred van Raaij, Erasmus University
Volume
SV - Historical Perspective in Consumer Research: National and International Perspectives | 1985
Share Proceeding
Featured papers
See MoreFeatured
Pursue Your Passions: Cultural Discourses about Consumer’s Heroic Wilderness Adventures
Nathan Warren, University of Oregon, USA
Linda L Price, University of Oregon, USA
Featured
Emotion, Scientific Reasoning, and Judgments of Scientific Evidence
Caitlin Drummond, University of Michigan, USA
Baruch Fischhoff, Carnegie Mellon University, USA
Featured
O4. Will Winning Always Encourage Risk Taking? The Effect of Competition Results and the Closeness of These Results
Beixi Wen, Renmin University of China
En-Chung Chang, Renmin University of China
Chunya Xie, Renmin University of China